Image credit:
Tumisu, Pixabay
Last week, I looked at ethics in general, and the
relations between moral obligations and human rights. Today, I’m going to try
to answer head-on the question: What is right, and what is wrong, for a human
being to do?
Where I came in
To list my first three conclusions from last week’s essay:
1)
Identity determines morality. Right and
wrong behaviours for a species of sentient beings are determined by the nature
of the species.
2)
Ethical equality. Among members of the
same species, what is right for one to do, is right for another to do under
similar circumstances, and vice versa.
3)
The natural law of humanity. There exists
a list of ethical obligations, which represent the behaviours natural to human
beings. This can be codified.
The second and third of these statements follow directly
from the first. And as evidence for the first, I gave you the behaviours of
different species co-existing in the same environment, such as waterfowl around
a lake. Their behaviours have a similar core, but each species has its own
variations too.
Our nature
In last week’s essay, I also stated my view of the present
stage of development of humanity as a species. I identified the main elements
of our nature as: To take control of our surroundings, to use them for our
benefit, and to leave our mark on them. To use our faculties of reason, to seek
to understand what we see around us and what we experience. To form ourselves
into social groups, and to organize them in such a way as to bring benefits to
everyone in them; and so, to provide a civilized habitat, in which we human
beings can live our lives to the full. To interact with each other using Franz
Oppenheimer’s economic means, “the equivalent exchange of one's own labor for
the labor of others.” And thus, to seek to co-operate in order to take control
of our surroundings.
I introduced these elements of our nature in an essay called
“The Rhythms of History,” back in late July. In which, I looked at our history
in terms of a series of forward-moving revolutions; interspersed with periods
of stagnation or backsliding, which result from counter-revolutions, or
reactions, launched by those that want to hold us back.
The elements I listed above are those aspects of our nature,
which have been most apparent during some of the best and most revolutionary
periods in our history. In particular, the first “age of reason” in ancient
Greece; the Renaissance; the second age of reason, otherwise known as the
Enlightenment; and the Industrial Revolution. They are the aspects of
ourselves, which have made us human beings as a species what we are today.
My plan of action
I dub the codified version of the natural law of humanity,
as at our present stage of development, “the Convivial Code.” I use the word
“convivial,” not only in its basic sense of living together, and in its sense
of being friendly and jovial (with a sub-text of feasting in good company!),
but also in the sense of “fit to be lived with.” Thus, convivial conduct is the
conduct of a human being, who is fit to be lived with in a civilization.
That said, to codify the natural law of humanity completely is
a monster of a task. Certainly not one which can be done by one individual, or in
just a couple of thousand words!
I shall, therefore, structure the rest of this essay in three
parts. First, I will make some general remarks about the Code. Second, I will
look at John Locke’s one-sentence statement of the law of Nature in his Second
Treatise of Government. And third, I will list the obligations, which I see as
my best shot so far at capturing the salient features of the Code.
General features of the Convivial Code
The Convivial Code will be an ethical code of conduct, which
encapsulates the natural law of humanity. It will be, in essence, a touchstone
for humanity, at the stage at which we are today. It will be independent of any
particular culture, religious belief or non-belief. It will constitute a core
set of standards of “civilized” behaviour for human beings worth the name.
It will make allowance for those exceptional situations, in
which strict adherence to the Code may not be practical. Self-defence and
defence of others, in particular, will under certain specified circumstances be
seen as valid reasons for deviating from the letter of the Code.
People who make every effort to keep up to the standards of
the Code, and so to obey the natural law of humanity, make themselves
convivial, or “fit to be lived with.” Together, these people constitute what I
call the “convivial community.” What binds this community together is a shared
willingness to behave convivially. I equate this with the “great and natural
community” of John Locke, to which all human beings would naturally belong, if
it were not for “the corruption and viciousness of degenerate men.” (And degenerate
women).
The opposite, behaviours that violate the Code, I call disconvivial
behaviours. I also sometimes use the term “real wrongdoing” for such
behaviours, or even inhumanity. For those that fail to measure up to the
core standards of human behaviour, most of all if they do so habitually or in
large matters, are failing to behave as human beings. They are degenerates. Thus,
they are not fit to be accepted into any civilization of human beings worth the
name.
The Code has nothing necessarily to do with “laws” as they
are made today. It cannot, and must not, be invented – and most of all, it
cannot be made by edicts of any cabal of politicians or their hangers-on. That route,
as Locke identified, results in laws that are often no more than “the fancies
and intricate contrivances of men, following contrary and hidden interests put
into words.” Instead, the Code must be discovered, by examining and
understanding ourselves, our cultures and our history.
One major way in which the Code will differ from systems of political laws is that, for long periods, sometimes even over many centuries, the Code will be timeless. So, once set up, it needs no legislative. Changes only become necessary when circumstances occur which have not been envisaged before, or human nature itself changes, or new knowledge becomes available about what it is. And these events are rare. For example, the latest change in human nature came with the Industrial Revolution. Because of this, absent such events, the Code will be applicable retrospectively.
Once constructed and agreed – and that is a monster of a project in itself – the Code must be tried out in practice, very likely in prototype communities. These can then be used as seeds towards its wider and wider adoption. Other aspects to be hammered out would include the procedures for determining when a change is necessary to the Code, for specifying the changes, and for introducing a new version of the Code.
John Locke’s summary
Here is the text of John Locke’s one-sentence summary of the
Code, from §6 of
his Second Treatise. “The state of Nature has a law of Nature to govern it,
which obliges every one, and reason, which is that law, teaches all mankind who
will but consult it, that being all equal and independent, no-one ought to
harm another in his life, health, liberty or possessions.”
In what sense did Locke mean that we are all equal? He
certainly didn’t mean a socialist idiocy like equality of economic outcome.
Indeed, he wrote: “I cannot be supposed to understand all sorts of ‘equality.’ Age
or virtue may give men a just precedency. Excellency of parts and merit may
place others above the common level.”
No: he meant ethical equality! In the same sense as I do. For
he said, of the law of Nature: “What any may do in prosecution of that law,
every one must needs have a right to do.” As to being all independent, it is a
fact that each of us has our own body, our own mind, and our own will. It is up
to each of us, as an individual, to live our lives as best we can. And as long
as we behave as human beings, no-one should have any right to stop us doing so.
As to “no-one ought to harm another in his life, health,
liberty or possessions,” Locke is saying: no killing of human beings, no
physical assaults, no infringing on others’ rights or freedoms, and no stealing
or destruction of property. That’s a pretty good first shot at a law of
civilized behaviour for human beings, is it not?
And yet, when we look at the actions of leaders,
functionaries and hangers-on of political states around the world today, we see
that a lot, even most of, the time they fall seriously short of this mark.
Indeed, wars, physical assaults and destruction of property are built into the very
foundations of the “Westphalian” states we suffer under. As is taxation, which
enables the politically rich to extort earnings or property, or both, from the
politically poor. And violations of our human rights and freedoms have become all
but routine. Such as the “on-line safety act,” and facial recognition cameras
in the public space.
My own contribution – “the Code lite”
It may not surprise you, at this point, to find that I have
been working for many years towards my own best shot at writing the Convivial
Code.
As I explained in last week’s essay, I see ethical codes in
terms of lists of obligations to be kept to. Therefore, that is how I will
express my approximation to the Code. As to its level of detail, I am aiming
somewhere in between John Locke’s one-sentence statement, and a full treatment,
which I would expect to extend to many dozens, if not hundreds, of pages.
I have expressed my version, which I will call “the Code
lite,” as a list of 25 obligations. Of these, the first seven are positive
obligations, to which the individual must keep if they are not to
violate the natural law of humanity. The next four are expectations – things
which the individual must strive to do. The remainder are negative
obligations or prohibitions; things which the individual must not do. In
each of these, the exceptional situations I discussed above, like self-defence,
which may justify a deviation, must be borne in mind.
And I will define here what I mean by justice and injustice,
and the adjectives just and unjust. By “justice,” I mean what I
call “common-sense justice.” That is, the condition in which each individual is
to be treated, over the long run, in the round and as far as practicable, as he
or she treats others. And when I use the words “just” or “unjust,” I mean in accordance
with, or not in accordance with, common-sense justice.
As I did above with John Locke’s version, you may care to
contemplate how well the behaviours of those in positions with political power
today, whether they are publicly visible or not, measure up to these
obligations, expectations and prohibitions.
The positive obligations
1)
Respect the human rights and freedoms of all
those who respect your equal rights and freedoms.
2)
Always seek the facts on any matter, and tell
the truth as you understand it.
3)
Be honest, candid, straightforward and sincere
in all your dealings.
4)
Take responsibility for the reasonably
foreseeable effects on others of your voluntary actions.
5)
If your voluntary actions cause objective and
unjust harm or inconvenience to others, you have an obligation to compensate
them.
6)
If you engage in activities that impose a risk
of harm on others, you must have in place resources to enable you to compensate
them if such a harm eventuates.
7)
Always practise what you preach.
The first of these obligations, obviously, does not answer
the question “precisely what are the rights and freedoms, which everyone must
respect?” This I regard as something which must be fleshed out in the process
of detailing the Code. But in outline, any right in any of the major lists of
rights, from Magna Carta, via the 1689 bill of rights and the 1791 US bill of
rights, to the UN declaration and the European Convention, must be checked to
see if it is in reality a valid right. And if it is, it must be back-to-backed
with an obligation or set of obligations, in the way I explained in last week’s
essay.
The remaining obligations are more self-explanatory. They
require close adherence to truth and honesty. They impose on you a responsibility
for what you do to others; require you to provide compensation if you unjustly
harm others; and impose a restriction on the risks to which you may subject
others.
The last obligation is, perhaps, the most important of all.
For hypocrisy – preaching that in a given situation, people should act in one
way, yet yourself acting differently – is a sure sign of disconviviality.
The expectations
8)
Strive to be independent, self-reliant and
rational in all your thoughts and actions.
9)
Always strive to carry out what you have
knowingly and voluntarily agreed to do.
10) Always
strive to behave with objectivity, justice, integrity and good faith.
11) Strive
to be tolerant of all those who are convivial and tolerant towards you.
These are all couched in terms of striving to meet an
obligation, rather than simply meeting it in every situation. This reflects the
fact that these expectations are, for many if not all of us, harder to keep to
than are obligations such as truthfulness, honesty and straightforwardness.
The prohibitions
12) Don’t
bully anyone, or commit any aggression against anyone’s life, person or
property.
13) Don’t
interfere in other people’s lives without a good, objectively justifiable
reason.
14) Don’t
unjustly do to others what they do not want done to them.
15) Don’t
intentionally do or aggravate injustice.
16) Don’t
promote, support, co-operate with or condone any unjust violation of human
rights or freedoms.
17) Don’t
promote, support, make or enforce any law that harms, inconveniences, or
violates the rights or freedoms of, innocent people.
18) Don’t
seek to control others through emotional manipulation or obfuscation.
19) Don’t
put any obstacle in the way of the economic free market, or unjustly deny
anyone’s access to it.
20) Don’t
unjustly deny others the right to make their own decisions in thought or
action.
21) Don’t
deny anyone the presumption of innocence, or require them to prove a negative.
22) Don’t
try to take more from others than you are justly entitled to, or to impose
costs on others that bring no benefit to them.
23) Don't
pick favourites, or operate double standards with anyone.
24) Don't
recklessly impose harm, or unreasonable risk of harm, on others.
25) Don’t
willingly let yourself become a drain on others.
Would you agree with me, that these are all things which
every civilized human being should refrain from doing? If you agree, would you
also agree that under today’s conditions, we are all of us, again and again, subjected
to violations of many, if not all, of these prohibitions?
To sum up
In this essay, I have made my best attempt to “put some
flesh” on what I call the Convivial Code, the ethical code which specifies the
natural law of civilized humanity. I have noted some of its general
characteristics. I have given John Locke’s one-sentence summary of it, and my
own “Convivial code lite” of 25 obligations. And I have suggested, for your
consideration, that the behaviours of those with positions of political
privilege today are very, very far from satisfying either John Locke’s summary
of the Code or mine.